THE PROMISE OF EXPRESSION TO THE 'INEXPRESSIBLE
CHILD' : DELEUZE, DERRIDA AND THE IMPOSSIBILITY
OF ADULT'S LITERATURE
Vadim Linetski
"... Twins ... cannot be described because we should be sure to be
describing the wrong one." J.M.Barrie Peter Pan
"A mere resemblance, no doubt. Only a discourse of the sophists' type
would be so indecent as to misuse it. But to misuse a resemblance, isn't
that to present it as an identity, isn't it to assimilate? One can also
ponder
the reasons for resemblance as such." Derrida On the Name
As the tale goes, there are many poststructuralisms. But are they compatible,
can they co-exist? Apparently, the answer is yes, meaning that the differences
within poststructuralism evidence the validity of its basic claims as regards
the irreducible heterogeneity. In other words, it is crucial to the whole
enterprise to preserve heterogeneity within theory in order to ensure its
appeal for the profane world without. And yet already the fact that the
becoming-fashionable of the Deleuze/Guattarian version is concomitant with
the demise of the deconstructive one should give us pause. However, a certain
intellectual effort is necessary in order to divulge in what appears to
be a historical contingency the workings of the logic which is the logic
of the poststructuralist difference itself.
If there should be a difference between Derridaean diffrance and Deleuzean
diffrence, between the parergonal n+1 and the schizoid synthesis of "...
and ... and...", then first and foremost from the standpoint of socio-political
application: as is generally believed, the fault of deconstruction is precisely
its inability to contribute anything to the ethico-political debate fostered
by the urgent necessity to hear the (repressed) voice of minorities, to
secure for them the possibility of expression (cf. Holub; Weimer).
The imperative has nothing surprising about it. If the (revolutionary) deterritorialization/reassemblage
should not wind up with an act of exclusion/scape-goating which grounds
logocentric tradition, then the new assemblage has to be an over-inclusive
system (Deleuze, Logic 203-204; Kristeva 214-218). However, the over-inclusiveness
runs the danger of collapsing into/merging with the logocentric notion of
wholeness. The only way to avoid this danger which postmodernism is able
to imagine is to ground excess in lack, in the primordial need for the other,
i.e. to define excess negatively: as an excess of lack/need. But by the
same token the system thus advanced comes to be grounded in impression,
rather than in expression, for the Otherness which comes first mutilates
the subject, impresses upon it a trace. Since the trace-inscription is an
infinite process, an act of expression itself is infinitely postponed. It
follows that on these premises the world (read: the Third World, the world(s)
of minorities) is only promised an expression but in actual fact
exists outside of expression, cannot still express itself. The problem which
will be addressed in this paper is whether, if at all, the promise of expression
can be realized. But first of all let us see whose promise is it that we
are speaking of?
The notions of trace and inscription seem to be unambiguous
pointers. Since they are inscribed in the concept of pharmakon, it
is rather tempting to conclude that the Derridaean model, whatever its deconstructive
merits, fails to produce an effective alternative. In fact, the applications
of the scapegoat-model explain how the images produced for mass consumption
are impressed upon the public mind (cf. Feldstein 1996) but have nothing
to say about the latter's expressing itself. This fact alone suggests that
the fault may well lie with the pharmakon itself which fosters the misrecognition
of logocentric strategies.
The pharmakon is a foreign body in the body of tradition, an entity which
the tradition has tried but failed to expel. In other words, the possibility
of deconstruction is bound up with the impossibility to perform an act of
expulsion, of sacrifice: the tie is not severed irreparably, from time to
time the pharmakon returns: as a specter or ghost it haunts the tradition.
The question is whether this ghost deconstructively impresses itself upon
the haunted, or rather expresses it.
The scapegoating mechanism functions on the Lacanian mirror-stage where
an identification can only be a misidentification, a recognition - a misrecognition:
"Thus, monoculturalists manufacture the scapegoated other through an
oppositional process that is not dialectical but imaginary, since it is
brought into being at the level of sadistic fantasy that cannot be owned
by right-wing reactionaries intent upon disavowing aspects of their own
personality ... Neoconservatives ... are forced to disidentify with
any rebellious counter-identification that surfaces as a dissident counter-image"
(Feldstein 1996: 147; italics added). Logically, this can only mean that
the excluded scapegoats, or, actually, their images manufactured by the
dominant cultural forces, are the true expressions of these latter, their
better and/or true selves. Therefore, contrary to popular prejudice, not
only has deconstruction everything to do with ethics, it is an ethical
enterprise - at least so long as the current applications of grammatology
are concerned. Forsooth, the latter is a pedagogy (cf. Ulmer), unfortunately
in the patently humanistic sense of the term. For the narrative of deconstruction
is the didactic narrative of melodrama aimed at bringing the (logocentric)
villain to recognize his better (postructuralist) self. Since it may be
argued that ethics is not such a bad thing after all, let us more closely
attend to the poststructuralist pedagogy.
At the face of it there is a difference between the logocentric construction
and its deconstruction, and it is this difference which, to believe the
postructuralist advocates, makes all the difference in the world. The post-psychoanalytic
and post-deconstructive ethics is "an ethics of lack concerned with
the gap between signs and objects and how this gap is bridged"
(Feldstein 1996: 130; italics added). It is this gap, the space in-between
which poststructuralism bares and cherishes, whereas the production of the
unified phallogocentric selfhood is allegedly bound up with its erasure.
In Derrida's theory this gap is known as khora "which is neither
'sensible' nor 'intelligible'" (Derrida, On the Name 89) and
has exactly the function of making compatible heterogeneous series (80,92)
that Deleuze allots to his mot blanc (Logic 84) or lment vide
(214) that by virtue of its "non-belonging to either of the series
is their point of convergence, their 'differential'"(67; cf.39,49,55,124,140,198-202).
What it should allow for is the hypercompatibility which preserves the singularity
of heterogenous elements, that is, negotiates between difference and repetition
in a way allegedly subversive of the metaphysics of presence in which the
Western hermenutic project is rooted. The phallogocentric drive for an unambiguous
meaning is an attempt to erase the non-presence of khora signaled by the
gaps in the narrative. (Re-)read, say poststructuralist theorists, Freud's
case histories. Let us!
The authors of the celebrated volume In Dora's Case are in accord
that the gaps in Freud's account of Dora testify to Freud's failure to master
his own discourse as well as that of his patient (cf. Hertz 233; Ramas 152-158;
Sprengnether 254-277). Whence the celebration of gaps, silences, raptures
and other discontinuities as a distinctive features of an criture feminine
(cf. Bal, "Mise en abyme" 116-128, Lethal Love 88; Cixous
53; Craft-Fairchild 6; Gossy). However, it is sufficient to glance at the
history of Little Hans in order to divulge the real function of the khoraic
pause.
Since the ego-ideal/superego plays a prominent part in phobic performance,
it is not surprising that the mechanism of phobia is that of scapegoating,
splitting of the non-compatible elements which come to haunt the subject
in the manner of Derridaean pharmakon. The aim of the psychoanalytic cure
is to expose the phobic symptom not as a foreign body which impresses itself
upon the patient's mind but as a patient's own production, to wit, as a
pathogenic expression of his/her personality. The irony of the matter is
that to conceive of a phobic representation as an expression means to transform
the spectral pharmakonic structure of undecidability into a structure of
interpretability par excellence, to wit, into the Oedipal structure. The
sine qua non of this transformation is precisely the insertion of gaps into
the narrative of as well as on Hans.
This insertion is necessitated by the fact that the phobic representation
is an exaggeration, an excess: phobia makes use of the natural discrepancy
(Hans's relative smallness and the relative bigness of heavy, dray horses)
and exaggerates it. Logically, this means that if we conceive of phobic
exaggeration as a continuous process the patient would either gradually
cure him/herself (in a "natural" way by outgrowing the fear-provoking
objects or "culturally": by gradual familiarization1), or go mad, in both cases
escaping the analysis. And this is precisely why Freud has to punctuate
the narrative of Hans's illness with gaps, pauses, moments when phobia
is allayed or disappears (261, 263, 271, 333 etc.) and to subject his own
account to the same procedure in order to vindicate his writing on
Hans2
The result of this khoraic punctuation, of introducing discontinuities is
the impossibility to make head or tail of Hans's fear, for on Freud's own
premises, only a constant/continuous tension can produce unpleasure (1914:
151). Or, to be more precise, the only possibility of understanding now
left is precisely to conceive of the whole affair along the lines of the
poststructuralist "ethics of lack", which vainly strives to differentiate
itself from the Oedipal ethics. In other words, the Oedipal interpretation
is not just one among many other possible translations (of the discontinuous
narrative), as poststructuralism would like us to believe (Weber, Institution106),
but the only interpretation precisely because it acts-out the movement of
its production. The irony of the matter is that it is this theatricality,
so dear to the poststructuralist heart (cf. Weber "Einmal"), which
thwarts the subversive claims of rhizomatic anti- or contra-semiotics.
According to poststructuralist readers, the narrative gaps, silences and
similar discontinuities are the marks of repression (Craft-Fairchild 1993:
15, 165, 169). Basically, a repression is a failed repression, it testifies
to the desire to erase the gaps and the impossibility to do this. Whence
its hermeneutic value. This explains why the gaps inserted into the narrative
of Hans's illness resemble not so much bottomless abysses as broken bridges,
for their function is to tame the excess, to introduce an element of expressivity
into the phobic representation. But by the same token the expression remains
underdeveloped. In Freud's case this vindicates the recourse to childhood
as a proof text of psychoanalytic theory in general, that of neuroses in
particular: the neurotic is the one who has remained a child, who has refused
to grow up. However, precisely this model is what Deleuzean semiotics, which
heralds as a discarding of Oedipus and repression, boils down to, for the
gap (lment vide) from which "one speaks", i.e. which allows
for expression, is an element "of one's own sous-dveloppement soi
/under-development to or within oneself/" (Deleuze, Pourparlers
30). Little wonder, then, that after everything has been said and done by
way of elaborating the concept of "minor literature" (cf. Kafka),
Guattari concedes that the latter as well as "minor discourse(s)"
in general, can be seen only "in its nascent state" ("Pragmatic/Machinic"),
to wit, in a state of an underdeveloped discourse, whose subject is doomed
forever to remain a child, a poststructuralist Peter Pan.
As Jacqueline Rose would have it, the case of Peter Pan testifies to the
impossibility of children's fiction (1984: 1) insofar as "there is
no child behind the category 'children's fiction', other than the one which
the category itself sets in place, the one which it needs to believe is
there for its own purposes" (10). That is, the child is an objectified
image, a cultural myth: "suppose, therefore, that Peter Pan is a little
boy who does not grow up, not because he doesn't want to, but because someone
else prefers that he shouldn't" (3). The brute fact is that it is the
poststructuralist strategy which, aiming to remove this patriarchal prohibition,
imposes it far more effectively than the tradition was ever able to do.
Barrie's narrative, says Rose, at one and the same time confirms the patriarchal
paradigm and deconstructs it (141) in the same way and manner as the women
writers of the last two centuries did (Craft-Fairchild 1993: 164). In both
cases deconstruction is collated with khoraic gaps (Rose 1984: 16) , moments
when "there is no clear distinction between the narrator and the child
/or woman/ he /or she/ describes" (68). Consequently we cannot proceed
without deciding whether and to what extent these gaps are intentional,
for it is the problem of appropriation on which the theory of a double-voiced
discourse stands or falls (cf.Craft-Fairchild 21-22,164-167). In other words
the recourse to cultural studies, far from being a break with deconstruction
(cf. Brantlinger), is inscribed in, or even prescribed by the deconstructive
quest. Momentarily we shall see that this problem turns out to be an impasse
of deconstruction as well as of cultural studies 3.
To make of an Oedipal repression a tool of deconstruction we have to assume
that the discontinuities are unintentional, unconscious 4, i.e. to conceive of them as instances of Deleuzean
pre-subjective expressionism. The irony is that in so doing we have to conclude
that the latter produces the "good form" (Barrie) which is the
form of all logocentric myths, that of the childhood included.
"The fundamental desire, or even fantasy" which underpins the
myth of Peter Pan is the desire for "the eternal return of the same
(the same child and the same literature) which has been one of the drives
behind the very persistence of a work like Peter Pan"(Rose 1984:
133). The paradox is that so long as we are bent to treat Peter Pan
as "one of the most salient representatives" (134) of the mentioned
desire we have to concede that neither Freud's unconscious nor Deleuze's
reformulation of the Nitzschean eternal return as a difference qua repetition
(1968) offer "a decisive challenge to /the idea of/ sameness",
to "the idea that psychic life is continuous, that language can give
us mastery, or that past and future can be cohered into a straightforward
sequence, and controlled" (134). Witness the perfectly Deleuzean manner
of Peter Pan's "becoming an animal".
The animal in question is a crocodile that had swallowed a clock which continues
to tick in his belly. On his way to rescue the children captured by Captain
Hook Peter "decided to tick, so that wild beasts should believe he
was the crocodile and let him pass unmolested ... Peter reached the shore
without mishap, and went straight on; his legs encountering the water as
if quite unaware that they had entered a new element. Thus many animals
pass from land to water, but no other human being of whom I know ...
He had ticked so long that he now went on ticking without knowing that he
was doing it" (Barrie 1993: 122; italics added). Obviously the "becoming
a crocodile" which implies a regression on a pre-subjective, unconscious
level would have satisfied Deleuze. However, in Barrie's narrative this
becoming is synonymous with the acquisition of the "good form"
which, equally, is incompatible with the conscious ego 5. Ironically, this is precisely how the Western
tradition has always conceived of aesthetic activity: the best art is the
one that is unaware of its being art. Whence the place allotted to the notion
of imitation/mimesis and the celebration of the artistic as an eternal childhood:
the child who is neither self-conscious nor self-reflexive is so close to
nature that it can express the latter in a natural way. The current belief
which gave rise to the cultural studies is that in order to deconstruct
this myth it suffices to bare the (natural) "good form" as a cultural
construction (cf. Wood), to expose "the artificial at the very heart
of the most humanistic of discourses, the artistic" (Wills 13). To
do this means to show that the acquisition of the "good form"
is never "good" enough, that the promise of eternity implied in
our notion can never be maintained. Which is to say that to break "good
form" is to break the life-continuity, to introduce a gap. The problem
is, however, that the "good form" itself derives its seductive
power from being precisely such a break/gap: childhood and its adult substitutes
(vacations etc.) are intervals, pauses, gaps. At its Deleuzean and Derridaean
best poststructuralism is able to challenge the logocentric adversary only
at the level of the latter's promise that these pauses are in the nature
of things, that they are regular, that their return is guaranteed. Whence
the apparent undecidability which is as often hailed as it is rebuked: what
seems to be undecidable is whether the difference between logocentric and
poststructuralist paradigms is that of difference qua resemblance or resemblance
qua difference? (Derrida, Name 43).
Deleuze's diffrence is the difference between two kinds of repetition: the
one which reconfirms the moral and natural law and the other which transgresses
both (1968: 9), "the hazardous repetition as difference without regularizing
concept" (363). As J.Rose suggests, the logocentric myth, for instance
the myth of Puer Aeternus, hinges vitally upon the first kind of
repetition. As Barrie's narrative shows, it is the second Deleuzean repetition
which makes of Peter Pan the modern incarnation of the mentioned myth.
The seductive power of Peter Pan, of the logocentric myth in general, is
the seductive power of the "repetition without concept", to wit,
of the Derridaean letter, and stems from the fact that it/he "does
not always arrive /return/ at /the promised/ destination" (Derrida
1988: 201; original italics). Having once promised Wendy/nostalgic adult
reader to return in order to take "Wendy for a week every year to do
his spring cleaning" (143), Peter sometimes returns, sometimes forgets
to. Thus the gaps are everything else than "gut tempeririert":
rather than being "measured" they are rythmic (Deleuze 1968: 33).
In other words, precisely the insecurity of Peter's returning next year
secures the children for culture/society and, by the same token, transforms
Peter into a myth: if he would not have forgotten to return the children
would have never begun to doubt his existence, would never have grown up.
Which explains why the poststructuralist throw of the dice (repetition without
concept) fails to eliminate the Oedipal structure. The only sense in which
we are allowed to speak about the deconstruction of the Oedipus complex
in schizoanalysis is qua its resolution in a most conventional way.
If "it is so easy to give an Oedipal reading of Peter Pan"
(Rose 35), then because the main narrative prop, Peter's rivalry with Captain
Hook, so obviously resembles the Oedipal rivalry with the Father figure.
From this standpoint, Peter's killing the pirate is what makes of the tale
the celebration of a fantasy of eternal childhood, i.e. corroborates Rose's
claims. However, the matter happens to be a bit complicated due to the fact
that this rivalry is depicted as rivalry not over the mother, but over the
"good form".
If the latter was to remain Peter's property (cf. Deleuze 1969: 32-33),
the brunt and thrust of our preceding discussion would have been of the
sophists' type. However haphazard, provisional and inconstant the moments
of acquisition of the "good form" might be, it would have been
still possible to argue that Peter is inconstant and forgetful as a true
child of nature, as nature itself. Even the fact that the "good form"
is a temporal structure of Delezean "immaterial event" (1969:
14-17) rather than the spatial one of Lacanian Imaginary order, could not
have really improved matters: our analysis still would have remained open
to suspicions that we are exploiting mere resemblances. To make matters
worse Barrie's narrative, at first glance, seems to justify these suspicions,
for Captain Hook's, in fine, the adult's, inability to acquire the "good
form" any more and his "retained passion for it" (115) is
precisely what seems to make of Peter an object of ardent nostalgic desire,
i.e. triggers logocentric myth-making. Consequently, to maintain our charge
we have to disappropriate Peter, that is to break/split the "good form"
in a properly Deleuzean manner by inscribing "difference in the very
heart of the differentializing differential itself" (1968: 154). Fortunately
for us, this disappropriating inscription happens to be the outcome of the
Oedipal rivalry in Barrie's novel.
"We had one last triumph, which I think we need not grudge him (Hook).
As he
stood on the bulwark looking over his shoulder at Peter gliding through
the air,
he invited him with a gesture to use his foot. It made Peter kick instead
of stab.
At last Hook had got the boon for which he craved.
'Bad form,' he cried jeeringly, and went content to the crocodile"
(130)
Thus the Father retains the last word. The irony of the matter is that it
is the poststructuralist readers who allow him to do this once and for all.
"The paradoxicality of true repetition", says Deleuze, "is
that 'once' stands for 'all' /une fois pour toutes/" (1968:
127). Having failed once to maintain the "good form", Peter is
disappropriated forever: we cannot claim that he has ever possessed or would
have ever possess it. Appearances notwithstanding, this does not mean the
immortalization of desire and the endangering of the law but the immortalization
of the latter and the deconstruction of the former.
Paradoxically put, the lment paradoxal which makes the different
trends of poststructuralism converge and resonate is the structuralist Lacanian
theory of desire that stresses the complicity of the latter with the law:
"aggression against the Father is at the very heart of the Law ...
the Law is in the service of the desire that Law institutes through the
prohibition of incest" (1996: 418). As we shall momentarily see, Derridaean
deconstruction as well as Deleuzean schizoanalysis are "forms of psychotherapy
which infantilizes adults, without recognizing children any better"
(418).
Ironically, thus far nobody has bothered to not that, from the Lacanian
standpoint, on which poststructuralist theories of visuality so heavily
rely (cf. Brennan and Martin; Salecl and Zizek; Silverman), all the talk
about the patriarchal reduction/subjection of the child/woman to an object
of the male's desiring gaze/discourse (Rose 2) makes no sense because, according
to Lacan, the essence of desire is to have no object. Hence in order
to be able to speak "of what the adult desires ... in the very act
of construing the child as the object of its speech" (2) we have precisely
to disobjectify the object, in case of Peter Pan, to disappropriate him,
i.e. to expose him as lacking and desiring the same what the Father figure
lacks and desires. Since this is what Lacan's dictum "desire is desire
for desire" (418) implies, it follows that the party which really has
reasons to criticize Lacan for promulgating political sexism is the neoconservative
phallocrats and not the feminist theorists, for the (in)famous bar which
grounds the discourse of desire privileges the woman. In effect, logically,
the threat of castration can only bar the subject from speech - the boy
that has something to loose more surely than the girl that does not. So
long as castration is a door to civilization, the boy, prompted by the instincts
of self-preservation, is more likely to reason that, whether or not the
mother has a penis, in any event it is far more secure to renounce speech
as such. The unruly subject of the patriarchal Law is a male one,
for, contrary to what the feminist orthodoxy would like us to believe, in
case of a female little or nothing bars her access to the symbolic
order. The problem of patriarchy is therefore how to force the male subject
to speak? The only solution is exactly the one suggested by poststructuralism,
namely to conceive of parole as prior to langue, of jouissance
as prior to desire. And this is what Lacan does in his Twentieth Seminar.
Witness his stress that the unconscious is structured not so much as the
language in the sense of Roman Jacobson as "maternal lalangue"
(1975: 126). Unfortunately, the solution appears promising only at first
glance.
For to foreground jouissance means to allow for total satisfaction, to wit,
for an incest, and in so doing to make of the emergence of civilization,
let alone of the discontent in it, a puzzle. In other words, if within the
discourse of desire the male subject has all reasons to fear to speak,
within the discourse of jouissance he has no reason to speak at all.
To avoid this impasse we have to privilege the position of the female subject,
for in case of the female subject the coercion to speech seems to be no
coercion at all. In effect, the Penisneid which is a feminine analogue
of the incestuous wish of the male can be satisfied in a most natural way,
to wit, by an act of giving birth. As the psychoanalytic orthodoxy would
have it, the child is a woman's substitute for the penis she lacks, i.e.
a fetish, an imaginary product. Therefore to possess it, to achieve jouissance
by its means seemingly does not imply a transgression of the Law. The irony
is that this solution implies the destruction of the Law, for to shift onto
the Imaginary plane means to admit that the phallus can signify only as
a fetish, to wit, that it does not signify at all. In other words, whatever
the hierarchical reversals the problem would have haunted psychoanalysis
up to this day, were it not for the schizoanalytic "discourse of support"
(Derrida) which is nothing else than an attempt to fulfill the promise of
conventional psychoanalysis.
As we have seen, the trouble emerges the moment desire is allotted the role
of the motor of Symbolic signification, is posited as a desire for recognition
and at the same time is barred from ever attaining satisfaction (Lacan
1996, 418-419). Since to recognize is to name (419) this means nothing else
that the Symbolic Order leaves no chance for expression. Consequently, to
juxtapose desire and jouissance is not enough: the only way to trigger the
process of signification is precisely to split Lacanian desire into two
desires (the one to be named, the other - a blank desire, forever unsatisfied,
striving for more) and to introduce jouissance as their (dis)connecting
conjunction: "desire lacks nothing and ever strives for more"
(L'Anti-Oedipe, 335). Which means that the discourse of the Anti-Oedipal
desire is the underdeveloped discourse capable of infinite development.
The irony is that the advanced concept of desire applies all too well to
the discursive strategy of "minor literary genres", say, of children'
fiction as exemplified by F.H.Burnett's Little Lord Fauntleroy, but
compels us to see in this strategy, i.e. in the Anti-Oedipal desire
itself, an expression of the mute phallogocentric world unable to name itself.
In effect it is precisely Cedric's "sous-development a soi"
which forces him to play the role of the mediator between the discourse
of his mother and grandfather, to bring about their reconciliation which
bridges/satisfies their desires (grandfather's desire for the lack and mother's
desire to be recognized/named) and yet leaves them to desire more. Far from
being scapegoated, to wit, excluded from the bliss of vnement incorporel
(Deleuze 1969: 15, 160), Cedric also has his share in it. However, the entrance-ticket
is paid by the underdevelopment of his own discourse: his function as a
mot blanc (Deleuze 1969: 55) is to allow the adult's wishes impress
themselves upon him and eventually give them an inadequate articulation.
The same holds for Little Hans and Peter Pan: only the child can ensure
the convergence and resonance between heterogeneous discourses of (conflicting)
adult's desires. The child is welcome - not as an object of gaze but as
a mouth-piece/mediator
6. Meaning that
the myth of the child's innocence which, as Rose was quite astute to point
out, is the linguistic myth (42-66) does not have anything to do with the
authenticity of expression: rather the child is admired for its mysterious
ability to express anything at all in the world where the Law allows only
for impression, since, as Freud has taught us, it is the impression (introjection)
of adult's voices (those of parents, tutors) which produces super-ego/conscience
(1914: 163). As a result the adult world, the discursive world of desire,
to wit, of the Symbolic Order, by necessity appears as the world of silence,
muteness wherein the child is bound to be kept from growing up, for only
from the position of Puer Aeternus a subject can hope to utter anything.
Which means precisely the universal infantilization of which Lacan has warned
us and to which he himself was the first to fall prey. And yet this is not
the last word of poststructuralism. Nor it is ours.
Suppose, say poststructuralist theorists, that the child's expression is
deliberately inadequate, that its discourse/tongue is forked, double-voiced
(Myers 1995), in short, that our little lords are active adepts of de Certeau's
"practice of everyday life". However striking the resemblance
between the latter and the theories of Derrida and Deleuze, it is not surprising
that thus far nobody has bothered to examine it, for such an endeavor would
question one of the fundamentals of current theorizing, namely the belief
that "taking in" (impression) is a form of "talking back"
(expression), that "subjects create themselves and their cultures ...
through collage", that "bricolage is a strategic resistance"
(68).
Obviously the rhizomatic anti- or contra-semiotic of Capitalism and Schizophrenia
the basics for which were laid in Repetition et Difference and
Logic du sense is an instance of bricolage, an over-inclusive system
of hyperconnectivity. However, the anti-Oedipal brunt and thrust would have
been impossible without allotting a more active role to the conjoining "element
of void", to the differential(izing) mot blanc. Now it is no
longer just "le verbe infinitif" (1969: 216): "'Between
things' does not designate a localizable relation going from one thing to
the other and back again /e.g. Cedric's role/, but a perpendicular direction,
a transversal movement that sweeps one and the other away,
a stream without beginning or end that undermines its banks and picks
up speed in the middle" ( Thousand 25; italics added) 7. So long as the "in-between"
remains passive it can foster the conjuncture between the two series only
at the price of its own effacement, meaning that the conjuncture itself
remains a "passive synthesis" with which Deleuze was still quite
satisfied in Logic du sense (142) and which, as we have just seen,
reinstates, or, more correctly, for the first time states, expresses the
Symbolic Law (of silence). Since the true repetition is said to be of a
theatrical order (1968: 30-34), the theater of early Deleuze is a traditional
one in which an actor effaces himself to make the on-stage and off-stage
heterogeneities resonate in the fundamentally impressive manner envisaged
by Stanislavsky. The deconstructive analogue offers deManian practice of
juxtaposing two series/readings, in themselves quite complete and developed.
Whence the dependence on an underdeveloped third party, on the latter's
inability to decide. Which means that appearances notwithstanding the undecidability
is an affair of infantilization and the theater in question is the theater
of the primal scene which baffles the child with the mutually exclusive
(for its level of comprehension) meanings (is this an act of violence or
caress?). Recently it has begun to dawn upon some feminists that aporia
is a method of silencing, one of the strategies of patriarchal subjection
(Trites 203). Which is precisely why the (theater) of logocentric semiosis
is a theater of phobic terror and dread that stem precisely from the primacy
of impression (of the Name/Law of the Father) over expression with the result
that neither affects can find verbal representation nor the latter does
express anything (Kristeva 42, 48): "By juxtaposing drives and discourse,
the pervert tends to neutralize them. As a result of this compromise, the
analyst sees the pervert's fantasy as a dramatization, a staging, or an
artifact" (22). In respect to his drives as well as his discourse the
pervert effaces himself but the result is a paraesthetic 8 acting-out which is nothing else than a rhizomatic
bricolage of verbal, pre-verbal and extra-verbal elements (cf. Maggiori
18). If the irony of Lacan's theory is that it hinges upon the inability
of the Law and its subject to express themselves, the irony of post-Lacanian
analysis stems from the fact that it allows the former to express itself
and consequently silences the latter.
According to Kristeva, especially in case of phobia, the success of the
cure depends upon the analyst's rejection of the temptation to identify
with the patient, since such an identification would make the neutralization
irrevocable: "analysts must ... put aside the neutrality and abeyance
that are all too similar to obsessional defenses" (62). However in
order to preclude the analysts's becoming a "subject-presumed-to-know"
this activity should be conceived of as "withdraw/al/ from the allocution"
(88), to wit, from the non-place of khora. Which boils down to an acknowledgment
that the act of scapegoating (for within the analytic discourse the analyst
is a scapegoat) is a self -willed one 9. And this is precisely why instead of transforming
the constative of the symbolic castration into a question (Kristeva 87-103),
experiment (Derrida 1995: 93) or problem (Deleuze 1969: 67-73), the withdrawal
10 makes the verbe
infinitif undergo a transformation into a phallic imperative ... according
to the best wishes of Lacan whose dictum "the woman does not exist"
(1975: 68) is scandalous only insofar as it exposes the Semiotic (lalangue)
as the expression of the Symbolic, i.e. far from barring the woman from
signification, bares her disobjectified/desubstantivized status as a signifier
which is "primarily an imperative" (33).
To allow for the element of intention in the parapraxis/practice of everyday
life means to stress the gap between an actor and his role, i.e. to conceive
of khora as "not referring to the gesture of a donor-subject, the support
or origin of something which would come to be given to someone" (Derrida
1995: 100). The paradox of simultaneous belonging and non-belonging of khora/lment
vide to the series which it coordinates (Deleuze 1969: 66; Derrida 1995:
126) evaporates the moment we remember that this is precisely the function
of the actor in Brecht's theater of political education to which theatricality
of Deleuze and Derrida's theories boil down 11. The didactic practice of making-strange presupposes
that the actor occasionally (read: khoraically, haphazardly) steps out of
the role and takes the place among the spectators. In so doing he triggers
the disequilibrium between the two images/series which were neutralized
by juxtaposition (cf. Deleuze 1968: 31, 140). As a result the auditorium,
viewed as a child to be educated, is forced to make a decision, moreover,
the right one. In like manner, the decision is brought about in Peter
Pan: as a mot blanc, to wit, as an actor in the mimetic theater,
Peter acts as a "'Betwixt-and-Between' who hovers between the island
of birds /Neverland/ and the nursery /in which we are all supposed to be/"
(Rose 27), but once he steps out of his role/"good form" he introduces
the disequilibrium between these two worlds equally seductive for children.
The result of his becoming the imperative forces us to read the Neverland
as an order never (to) land (there), i.e. to grow up, to renounce the Oedipal
struggle. Thus, the resolution of the Oedipus complex, impossible on the
mimetic scene, is achieved auf einer anderen Szene, to wit, in the
theater of poststructuralist theory which certainly breaks the "good
form" of the myth of eternal childhood, but in so doing leaves no chance
to conceive of non-didactic literature, to wit, of the literature for adults
12.
This outcome is only too logical, since the recourse to theater is implied
in the interpretive strategy which privileges gaps, ruptures, silences in/of
the narrative. Whence the vogue enjoyed by the notion of transference (cf.
Felman). Whatever its theoretical deficiencies, J.Rose's book supplies invaluable
historical material which allows us to clear the crucial problem that continues
to haunt cultural studies, namely the problem of appropriation of the most
subversive narratives by the cultural edifice. What enables this appropriation
is precisely the poststructuralist theatricality: it is not by accident
that Peter Pan "acquired that status /of a children's classic/
only by being performed as a play" (97). In order to appreciate this
fact let us remember that Freud's appropriation of Little Hans followed
the same route: only after having traced down Hans's phobia to a play (328-331),
Freud was able to claim the Oedipal interpretation and the resolution of
the castration complex. It follows that if the great subversive novels sooner
or latter are found palatable by the dominant culture then precisely due
to inscription of the theatrical structure 13. Meaning that the fact that theatrical adaptations
of "adult's" classics have never prevailed in the repertoire and
more often than not turn out to be failures testifies not to the complexity
of originals but to the superfluousness of adaptation of the texts which
have already adapted themselves. On the other hand, the fact that eventually
every children's novel has a theatrical version along with the fact that
theater is so rarely thematized in children's fiction, suggests that children's
fiction is far more threatening to the cultural edifice than is generally
believed. To prove our charge let us examine the elements which cannot be
placed on stage, and for that reason are the first to be effaced in theatrical
adaptation.
Significantly, the elements we are speaking of are central from the narratological
standpoint. Thus, the element which propels the narrative of Peter's rivalry
with Captain Hook is Peter's "cockiness" that is not effaced even
in sleep which is the khoraic gap par excellence, and it is this persistence
of exaggerative discourse which precludes the didactic twist, i.e. the victory
of the "better self" qua another "taming of the shrew"
14. Peter shares
this cockiness, which, rhetorically, is an exaggeration, with Cedric and
Hans, eventually, with all heroes of children's fiction. Certainly it is
all too tempting to try to explain it away as an instance of infantile narcissism
the celebration of which the logocentric myth of childhood is supposed to
be, since it is narcissism which makes the child an object of the desiring
gaze of the adult. And yet the obvious impossibility to make this feature
visible on stage should give us pause which will be prolonged if
utilize it to reread Freud's introduction of narcissism.
At first glance, Freud's paper does not contain anything challenging to
the poststructuralist assumptions, being as it is an attempt to expose narcissism
as an adult's construction, as an expression of his desire for a lost innocence,
an imaginary reward for unavoidable disappointments and discontents, a reward
"bound up with denial of an infantile sexuality" (157). The paradox
is that the would-be deconstruction of logocentric mythology reconfirms
its basic assumption as regards "the child's non-accessibility /Unzugänglichkeit/)
" (155) on which the myth-making so vitally depends. Put crudely and
bluntly, instead of the child which seeks the way to express itself we are
left with the "inexpressible child" 15. The result is the self-deconstruction of the
theory of infantile sexuality.
"One of the main premises" of the latter "is the assumption
of the primal narcissism of the child" (157) of which the adult's narcissism
is said to be a revitalization: "what the adult projects /von sich
hin projiziert/ as his ideal is a substitute for the lost narcissism
of his childhood when he was his own ideal" (161). However to speak
about an ideal means to evoke the notion of repression (160, 163), meaning
that if the child has an ideal there was repression at work. It follows
that the primal narcissism presupposes the developed ego and a successful
repression accomplished at a stage which even the Kleinians have never claimed
to access. Whence the necessity to keep narcissism distinct from repression.
The Oedipal, to wit, Lacanian way to do this is to conceive of narcissism
"as the amorous captivation of the subject by the image" (Laplanche
and Pontalis 256) and thereby to give primacy to impression with the result
sketched above. The Anti-Oedipal solution of Deleuze and Guattari
is the conflation of narcissism and auto-eroticism. This solution owes its
irony not so much to the fact that it happens to be quite an orthodoxical
one, being as it is propounded by Freud himself (256), but to the implied
denial of infantile sexuality, for narcissism thus conceived becomes an
affair of sublimation, especially in the context of polymorphous, i.e. essentially
object-oriented desire celebrated by Deleuze and Guattari 16. Fortunately, there is another possibility, namely
to surmise that primal and secondary narcissisms differ qualitatively: if
the latter allows only for impression, the former is essentially expressive.
The value of the suggested innovation, which has been always already practiced
by the authors of children's fiction, becomes immediately apparent in our
context.
As we have see, J.Rose's charge for the impossibility of children's fiction,
far from being original or whimsical, follows logically from the very premises
of poststructuralist theory which Rose adopts without questioning. And yet
the pursuit of this train of thought compels us to wind up with claiming
the direct opposite of the initial charge. Which means the self-deconstruction,
or better to say, the self-inhibition which postructuralism imposes upon
itself in order not to develop into deconstruction proper, not to grow up.
If children's fiction is impossible then because it never speaks to the
child, save the child within us (Rose 66-87; Kristeva 143). My contention
is that the gist of the matter is precisely not to speak to the child
but to allow the child to speak, to express itself. And this is precisely
what the primal narcissism as a writerly practice allows to do. Which explains
why children's fiction, along with "minor discourse(s)" in general,
if properly read subverts the discourse of desire, to wit, ethics and aesthetics
of the gap along with (post)pedagogy and hermeneutics grounded in the same
notion.
The fact that Peter's cockiness makes him present when he is absent (sleeping)
suggests that primal narcissism has nothing to do with the metaphysics of
presence. Witness the rage of the Father Figure, the rage which stems from
the fact that this narcissism makes the Father doubt his own existence:
"They /pirates/ were his /Captain Hook's/ dogs snapping at him, but,
tragic fi-
gure though he had become, he scarcely heeded them. Against such fearful
evi-
dence it was not their belief in him that he needed, it was his
own. He felt his
ego slipping from him" (78; italics added)
It remains to spell out the promise of this passage to the on-going debate
on the (im)possibilities of deconstructing the logocentric identities/gender
roles and reconstructing them beyond patriarchal paradigm.
If the most radical attempts in this direction constantly fail, then because,
contrary to general belief (cf. Cixous 48; Williams 134), it is not symmetry
but disbalance, disequilibrium what logocentrism has always been about.
To acquiesce with the Oedipal imperative means to concede to the exchange
which is far from being "equal", to accept the promise that the
losses are lesser than the gains. Were it not for this basic disbalance
of the discourse of desire, the founding act of logocentric epistemology,
an act which posits one term as a norm, the other as lacking, would have
been impossible17.
From this point of view it seems that Deleuze and Derrida by introducing
the third party as a khoraic element, as a "minimum shared by the real,
possible and impossible"18 (Logic 49; Name 99-100) highlight the way to circumvent
the difficulty. Suppose that the adult binary defines itself against the
childhood sexuality without excluding/scapegoating it. However, as
our recourse to Burnett's novel has proved, this would leave untouched the
most demanding problem - that of the third party expressing itself. For
the third discourse should remain underdeveloped, to wit, share the fate
of Kristevan "maternal". Ironically, critiques leveled at this
notion (Lichtenberg-Ettinger; Welchman; de Zegher) miss the point in the
same way and for the same reasons as the praises of it do (Doan and Hodges;
Jacobus). What invalidates both is inability to discern the real face of
the patriarchal adversary. The paradox is that, far from being "unsymbolizable",
Kristevan semiotic "maternal" is the only possible symbolization
of the patriarchal Symbolic Order. The only way to trigger signification
within the discourse of desire is precisely to conceive of the phallus as
an underdeveloped penis or as a clitoris, for only on these premises there
will be signification qua dissemination of meaning (the possibility to find
maternal or phallic imagery everywhere). Therefore it is not surprising
that the proper deconstruction of the patriarchal discourse of the symbolic
desire will start with subverting its semiotic effigy 19.
The subversive promise of the childhood sexuality stems from the fact that
the latter cannot stand for anything save itself. In other words, it undermines
the very mechanism of defining/identifying qua referring/relating, to wit,
that nucleus of rationality with which poststructuralism has tempered but
failed to do away
20. The subversion
is triggered by the simple fact that it is neither possible nor impossible
to define oneself against the child, for such a definition will have neither
semiotic nor anti-semiotic value. This impossibility leads to the confusion
between the Imaginary, Real and the Symbolic, as well as between repression,
denial and sublimation, ultimately, to the confusion between the basic concepts
of Western semiotics: something, nothing and anything 21. The paradox is that, far from becoming unnamable,
this confusion allows the child to express, or, to be more precise, to represent
itself, and to do this in a manner which the over-inclusive Deleuzean semiotics
was bound to find inadmissible. What primal narcissism boils down to is
the "representation hollowed out of expression /actually of impression/
... without which it could not be 'comprehended' save by chance /par
hazard/ or from without /i.e. by staging, fetishization/" (1969:
171). Obviously, the only way to make sense of a Freudian dictum which is
reiterated all the more frequently the less it is understood, is to conceive
of childhood's persistence as a constant gapless process of exaggerative
representation22,
and in so doing to list narcissism as another vicissitude of the drive,
the vicissitude which reaches beyond every kind of binarism, the sublime
poststructuralist binarism of differentializing difference included.
Works Cited
1 Since
the latter presupposes the former, and not the other way, as poststructuralism
would like it to be, it seems that the "social constructionist"
stance needs rethinking.
2 "Strictly speaking,
I have not learned from this analysis anything new" (377). Then why
bother to write it down, claiming moreover for the case history "exemplarity"
(377)? Alas, there were khoraic moments of an "analyst's despair"
when "the situation was quite obscure", when "analysis seemed
to make no progress" (289). Significantly, the same spectacle is staged
in one of Kristeva's recent analyses which attempts to transcribe the Oedipal
Law into more palatable terms (87-103). We shall soon return to this translation
to find its analogues by Derrida and Deleuze.
3 Cf. Guattari's interview
with C.Stivale:
CS: " Aren't there writers in previous centuries who can also reveal
these kinds of deterritorialization?
FG: Yes, certainly. It's a problem of familiarity. It's a little
difficult because . . . I may be saying something stupid, but it seems to
me that the examples of eruption of "becoming-minor" either have
been completely buried, or have taken on considerable importance. For
example, Jean-Jacques Rousseau could have been a minor writer, but on the
contrary, he has a fantastic importance (as perhaps Artaud will have tomorrow),
being classified as a principal writer of the twentieth century. I even
think this is presently taking place.So, I don't know. One really has
to see the "minor" a bit in its nascent state, one has to see
it a bit closer to oneself because the historically distant "minor"
has perhaps a different impact. I don't know, I haven't thought about
this question" (italics added). Significantly, Derrida, for his
part also has not considered the question which is the question of
poststructuralism's validity. No wonder that the problem of what in Nietzsche's
textuality has allowed for Nazi appropriation receives no answer (Ear
30-31).
4 "... the female
plot ... unconsciously ... rewrites the conditions and assumptions
of patriarchal culture" (Williams 138; italics added).
5 Cf: "Most disquieting
reflection of all, was it not bad form to think about good form?" (Barrie,
116).
6 So it is not surprising
that the recent reading of Little Hans focuses on Freud's relation with
the parents (Putner 1995).
7 Whence the impossibility
to differentiate between Deleuzean difference and the Derridaean diffrance
by stressing the temporality of the latter (Baugh). The irony is that the
alternative view (Descombes) does not differ from the former in the most
crucial point, ignoring the role of the khoraic gap in the production of
difference.
8 For a thorough critique
of the poststructuralist paraesthetic in its relation to Oedipality consult
Linetski 1996.
9 Derrida is quite
explicit on this point, failing, obviously, to think through the consequences
of his acknowledgement: "The duplicity of this self-exclusion, the
simulacrum of this withdrawal ... The specialists of the nonplace /khora/
and of the simulacrum /the forerunners of deconstruction/ ... do not even
have to be excluded from the city, like pharmakoi; they exclude themselves
by themselves" (Name 108).
10 Cf.: "What
is a question? ... a withdrawal" (Kristeva 88).
11 No wonder that
the pursuit of deconstruction makes the Brechtian underpinnings more and
more visible. Thus, Derrida's recent Spectres de Marx start with
quite Brechtian scene: ""Somebody, you or I, steps forward and
says: 'I'd like at last to learn and to teach to live' ... To learn and
to teach to live. A curious way to put it. Who should learn? From whom?
To teach to live, but whom? Are we ever to know? Are we ever to learn to
live? And first of all, what does it mean, 'to learn and to teach to live'?
And why, 'at last'?" (13).
12 Understandably,
contemporary critics are reluctant to concede that the it is the much hailed
theatricality of poststructuralist theory which compels them to regard didacticism
as an intrinsic feature of the poetics of children's fiction, which contested
on one level returns on the other (Rose 42-66). However in order to read
Burnett's novel as a didactic narrative we have to make an intertextual,
to wit, theatrical connection with Shakespeare's The Framing of the Shrew,
for the novel as it stands carefully avoids moralizing transformation of
Cedric into example to be admired and imitated even at the moments when
such a transformation could have been made without pushing the point (cf.
192).
13 Cf. the role of
theater in de Sade, Nabokov's Lolita, Joyce's Ullyses.
14 "Mastered
by his better self, he /Hook/ would have returned reluctantly up the tree
but for one thing. What stayed him was Peter's impertinent appearance as
he slept. The open mouth, the drooping arm, the arched knee: they were such
a personification of cockiness as, taken together, will never again, one
may hope, be presented to eyes so sensitive to their offensiveness"
(109). Significantly in the narrative celebrating "the amazing, pleasing
object ... the king member indeed! /guess which/" (Cleland 134) sleep
makes the innocent victim even more desirable (cf. 119-136).
15 The title of one
of the essays from Kristeva's recent New Maladies of the Soul, which
is pungently at odds with the text that treats the child's difficulties
with expressing itself.
16 The irony is that
the invalidation of the rebuke recently leveled at Deleuze and Guattari
for "adopt/ing/ the repressive hypothesis wholesale" (Flieger)
allows us to appreciate the critic's insight which cannot be maintained
if Deleuze/Guattarian discourse was tainted by the notion of repression.
That Anti-Oedipus is oedipal because Freud's Oedipus is already anti-oedipal
means that Deleuze and Guattari foster the resolution of the Oedipus complex
along the lines of sublimation for Freud's repression fails to resolve it
(whence the anti-oedipality of Freud's Oedipus).
17 Lynda Hart's critique
of Leo Bersani's "erotics of submission" (which, rhetorically,
is a hybrid conjunction of the underdeveloped and forked discourses) can
be usefully incorporated into our analysis. The author convincingly argues
that, all the rhetorical twists notwithstanding, Bersani's libido still
remains a masculinized one, i.e. posits male sexuality as a norm, and, consequently,
fails to sustain its promise to"take us out of the discourse of the
symptom into a nonreferential version of sexual thought", to wit, fails
to trigger "the representational crisis". However the proposed
amendments (elaborations on the theme "a lesbian strap-on as a perfect
simulacrum") turn out to be of no avail. Witness the concluding sentence
which is a perfect echo of the celebrated Lacanian definition of the Symbolic
Order: "In the lesbian imaginary, the phallus is not where it appears"
(Hart), Lacan: "For it can literally be said that something is missing
from its place only of what can change it: the symbolic" (1988, 40).
18 The triad is bound
to remain puzzling if we are not to align it with Lacan's Real, Imaginary
and Symbolic. And in fact, the Lacanians are compelled to allot the phallus
the khoraic role, acknowledging thereby its imaginary, to wit, semiotic
(in the Kristevan sense) status: "Lacan takes the imaginary
phallus as the 'at least one' /i.e. as a necessary minimum/ symbol of difference
... the seeming impossibility of psychoanalysis rests on the disbelief that
a minimal difference could give rise to maximal effects" (Ragland-Sullivan
72). As we have see, poststructuralists cannot be accused of this kind of
scepticism.
19 Against the backdrop
of the preceding discussion it is not surprising that the phallogocentric
narrative will foreground exactly the semiotic (in the Kristevan sense)
moments of the khoraic jouissance: "Louisa lay, pleas'd to the very
heart ... she went wholly out of her mind into that favourite part of her
body, the whole intenseness of which was so mightily fill'd, and employ'd:
there alone she existed, all lost in those delirious transports, those ecstasies
of the senses, which her winking eyes, the brighten'd vermillion of her
lips and cheeks, and sighs of pleasure deeply fetched, so pathetically express'd.
In short, she was now as mere a machine" (Cleland 195-196; italics
mine). If the reader bears in mind the role allotted to the extra-linguistic
semiotic material in the "disciplining and punishing/curing" discourse
of detection (psychoanalytic and otherwise), s/he will not need our prompt
to recognize the subversive force of Cedric's and Peter Pan's constancy
in maintaining the semiotic on the same exaggerated level (cf. Burnett 133,
137).
20 Witness the poststructuralist
notion of the self as relational (cf. Shapiro). Within the framework
of Peircean semiotics heralded as an alternative to the Sausserean structuralism
such self takes the place of the interpretant as a conjoining/articulating
in-between. Now it is precisely the focus on the interpretant which makes
Peirce's project appear far more rationalistic than the Saussurean one wherein
the arbitrary relation between signifier and signified has something mysthical
about it.
21 Eventually it is
the latter notion (khora) which is now in vogue. The unnoticed irony
is that the logical conclusion is the total aphanisis of Anti-Oedipal
desire since "the 'lost object' /which Deleuze does not want to
lose (1969: 187-188)/ ... is diffused so that any object and any
part of the body can become an erotogenic zone" (Hart; italics added).
22 The best illustration
of the subversive power of the constant exaggeration is Hans's phobia. If
we are at last to allow Hans to speak, and not to hear him (Punter 1995)
- so far as hearing is concerned Freud remains unequaled - we must believe
that he was afraid "of all horses" (283) instead of dismissing
his remark as a lie (283). The same exaggeration characterizes Cedric' discourse
who finds that everyone is not just his friend but his "greatest friend".
The way to tame the excess is to apply this term only to the grandfather,
i.e. to see in it a process of ideal-building, to wit, of impression. Whence
Deleuze's stress on the selectivity of the unconscious qua repetition with
difference ( 1968: 381).